I’m getting more in the thick of the
preparation of my new book, and as part of it I laid out the areas of social
research I needed to strengthen, among which there is a deeper understanding of
sociological action theory. I had already read Parsons’ The Social System some
years ago, and it has heavily influenced my own take on the working of society
(my construct of dominant reason is indeed a way of integrating voluntary
individual action with the influence of the group, which specifically has to
provide the arguments for the eventual justification of said action to others
-and to self-, along contractualist lines), but knew I had to delve deeper.
Before proceeding with the results of such delving, I have to say that Parsons
has been, in my humble opinion, very unjustly neglected by later sociologists
(he is not much quoted or acknowledged), and I cannot avoid sympathizing with what I suspect is the
real reason of his (relative) falling out of fashion. It has to do with a
dazzling representative of the next generation of his craft, the charismatic Charles
Wright Mills, devoting a good deal of one of his most known and influential
books (The Sociological Imagination) to savagely criticizing the
aforementioned Social System, because of its “unnecessary verbosity”.
Wright Mills presents a number of
long, torturous and yes, somewhat convoluted paragraphs of Parsons’ book
followed by a “translation” in much more direct and colloquial prose that
purportedly contains the same information, thus giving the impression that the
original work by Parsons is a pompous and ponderous accumulation of uninspired digressions,
apt to be summarized and streamlined in a paper of 10-12 pages without
substantial loss of accuracy (rather, what survived the process of pruning and
eliminating redundant and uninformative verbiage would be a bunch of
self-evident platitudes almost devoid of any scientific value). I may be
exaggerating the extent of Wright Mills critique (there was, may be, a tinge of
admiration and recognition for who was, after all, one of the giants of
American sociology when the Sociological Imagination was published) but
not much, as both figures were both characteriologically and ideologically
worlds apart (Parsons was a paradigm of the scholarly establishment, and quite
conservative and anti-communistic, couldn’t be seen without a flannel suit and
tie, and had a staid and cautious personal life, whilst the rambunctious Wright
Mills wore jeans and working boots, married four times -but only to three
different women!, drove to class in a motorbike -but not an American Harley,
but a German BMW, what a wuss!- and spent time in Cuba interviewing Fidel
Castro). Unsurprisingly, in the late sixties and seventies students the world
over identified with the latter, leaving the former’s theories aside (I myself
like to keep my copies of the Sociological Imagination and the Social
System side by side in my library as a little private joke). Which is a
pity, because sparkling and passionate as Wright Mills’ work may be, Parsons’
is by far more interesting, more illuminating and much deeper…
All this long introduction (and no reader
of this blog should be surprised that I sympathize and empathize with an author
accused of having a writing style considered by some young gun to be too wordy,
and too abundant in long paraphrases and circumlocutions) was just to say I
recently finished reading The Structure of Social Action, the other
major book by Talcott Parsons (in 2 scrumptious and eminently enjoyable
volumes), and that (more specifically, its discussion of previous sociologist
Émile Durkheim, which I have also extensively read, of course) got me thinking
in some remarks by one of my teachers (Amelia Valcarcel, we will get to her in a
subsequent post) in very illuminating ways. Let’s start with Parsons’
understanding of Durkheim first, and see if we can reach to Valcarcel’s
considerations in due time…
What we are reminded at the beginning
of the section of the Structure of Social Action devoted to the
discussion of Durkheim’s ideas is that he was a strict positivist. As
this feature will turn out to be of extraordinary importance for my argument,
we will need to deviate for a moment from our exposition of Parsons’
considerations of Durkheim, and expound what we understand such position to
entail. During the first third of the XX century, positivism (a position
championed first and foremost by Auguste Comte, the avowed teacher and
inspirator of Durkheim) coincided quite literally with what today we call (a
bit deprecatingly) “scientism”, and was an evolution of the (much older)
empiricist worldview. For empiricists (the basic psychological and ontological
scaffolding was designed and built by Locke, but the real meat and potatoes of
the complete and philosophically coherent system were developed by my old
friend Davey Hume), only those things that we can directly perceive through our
bodily senses can be said to “really” exist. Even what we would call “mental”
realities (“abstract” ideas, emotions, feelings, anticipations, memories, complex
theories, mathematical systems, flights of fancy in our imagination and
whatnot) are, according to empiricists, but a residue (or a re-elaboration of
residues) of impressions left by things that we have perceived a number of
times through our senses. As science developed in the XIX century the strictly
empiricist position became more and more difficult to sustain (Maxwell
equations showed quite conclusively the existence of a number of stubbornly
physical things, no hocus-pocus or fluffy fairy-dust here!, like
electromagnetic fields, charged particles, and subtle interactions, that our
feeble senses would never be able to perceive), and was thus replaced by the
positivism we are talking about: “Science” (at least the part of it that had to
deal with non-conscious elements of nature, also called “natural sciences”, Naturwissenschaften
in German) could exhaust the description of what was real and, vice versa,
only those elements of reality that could be described by said “science”, that
could be measured, that could be shown to conform to universal, parsimonious
rules, were deemed to be “really, truly, honest-to-God real”. All the rest
(first and foremost religious dogmas, of course, but once you start wielding
your positivistic axe, all of metaphysics, doesn’t matter how anticlerical it
may turn out to be, has to be discarded too).
I won’t go into the evident
self-contradiction that stares you in the face the moment you formulate either
empiricism or positivism (the discarding of metaphysics is itself a
metaphysical proposition, not empirically demonstrable, and not amenable to
being formulated, falsated or verified through anything remotely resembling the
scientific method), or dwell in the methodological quicksand it soon found
itself mired into (what has been called the demarcation problem: we can all
agree that physics is unimpeachably “scientific” and that astrology is not…
unfortunately, when we try to isolate the actual ways of doing physics, or
chemistry, or biology that should distinguish them and constitute the ultimate
explanation of such unimpeachability, so we could replicate them in other
disciplines, like psychology, or anthropology, or sociology to make them more
“scientific”, we find that the original “hard sciences” share a lot of the
quirks and biases and implicit and unfounded assumptions that plague the latter,
and we end up accusing the former of not being so scientific after all -see the
whole social constructivism line of thought). I’ll just point out that Durkheim
thought that the universe was composed only of three types of facts (all of
them observable, with the help of specific instruments that may magnify them,
if needs be): the “brute” facts of nature, the “mental” facts within the
individuals’ brains (which were, needless to say, reducible to the first, no
Cartesian whims here!) and the “social” facts, which constituted a third
category. Finally, we need to note that for him any proposition, to be true,
had to have a referent, to point to some existing fact or another (what after
Wittgenstein we would call a “denotative theory of language”).
The next element that Parsons draws
our attention to is that for Durkheim (contra most progressive thinkers of the
era and previous eras, like most philosophes, and the German left
Hegelians, Marx and Feuerbach first and foremost among them… but not
necessarily his teacher Comte!) religious propositions, being a manifestation
that could be found in all societies, in his own time and in the past, had to
be “true” (or they would have been eliminated). Now, they could not be true in
the sense of describing an element of reality not amenable to scientific
knowledge (because, remember, for him there could simply NOT be such elements).
So they had to describe something really existing, and the question is,
what could that be? it could not be facts of inert matter, as most of the
contents of religious dogmas were incompatible with what physics teaches of how
matter behaves (starting with the creation of the universe out of nothing, or
out of a primordial chaos, that is more or less shared by all religions and
would contradict either the laws of conservation of matter and energy or the
second principle of thermodynamics). It could not be mental facts either, as
what we know of human psychology is similarly incompatible with the most
salient aspects of most religions, from ancient totemism to more developed
“revealed” ones (from magical effects to miracles, prophecy and other types of supernatural
knowledge), which presuppose some capabilities at least in some persons (not
only founders, which can be assumed to be of a divine origin, but in selected
leaders of the church or chosen ones, be them shamans, priests, gurus, etc.) As
Parsons summarizes it (in page 413 of Volume I of the Structure of Social
Action):
At the outset of the book [Parsons is here discussing Durkheim’s
The Elementary Forms of Religious Life] he remarks that so persistent
and tenacious an element in human life as religion is inconceivable if the
ideas associated with it are pure illusions, that is, do not “reflect any
reality”. And so he starts with a critique of the schools of interpretation
which have, on the one hand, made religious ideas the primary element of religion
and, on the other, have sought to derive these ideas from men’s impressions of
the empirical world. This will be recognized as the typical approach of the
earlier scheme – the question what , from the point of view of the actor, is
the “reality” reflected in the ideas, the “representations” in terms of which
he acts.
You probably can already see where
this is leading: for Durkheim (in Parsons telling, and I think Parsons got it
right here) the propositions of religious dogma, since its earliest
manifestations (in totemism, as could be observed between Australian aboriginal
tribes as documented by mostly German anthropologists, so kind of a third-hand
account, but enough for him to assume that was a valid blueprint for every
religious expression and form that came afterwards) really referred to
the social reality, a somehow fuzzy concept that he had been championing since
his first writings as being a sui generis kind of entity, but with as
much claim to real existence as any lump of matter. And, if religious expressions,
religious feeling, even actions that could be construed as religious ritual,
all made reference to society, which is undeniably real, they could
safely be understood as being true, which is what he was really after.
Of course, a believer may see things
quite differently. When the Australian aboriginal chooses not to eat his
totemic animal, or refrains from having sex with someone from the wrong totem,
he is not complying with those prescribed behaviors because he feels an
irrational respect (and awe and veneration) for the enhanced powers of the
social group. Or not only that (because, if that were all he had in mind, we
would lack a non-circular explanation of his behavior, specially the part of it
more detrimental to everyday survival). When the Dervish dances and reaches a
mystical feeling of unity with the divine that created the universe he does not
consider that he is just very attuned to the traditions and myths and (somewhat
deluded) worldview of his fellow believers with which he constitutes a collective
unit (society!) able to exert much more power over their shared environment than
what he alone could. When a Christian of whatever denomination participates in
communion he doesn’t think about the holy form as a symbol of the unity of the
group (or at least he shouldn’t only think that; in our own very
disenchanted age it is a valid question what exactly does an enlightened
citizen thinks he is doing by eating the wafer, and I wouldn’t discard in most
cases it is something closer to the Durkheimian affirmation of group belonging
and respect for the group’s traditions than to the direct access to the
numinous, to the “irreducibly, entirely other” in Karl Otto’s terms, that
orthodox theology tells him).
Be it as it may, the key aspect that
caught my attention in Parsons interpretation of Durkheim is how the former
sees the latter as using religion to complement an understanding of human
motivation that would make the stability of social groups almost impossible to
explain in its absence. Durkheim’s positivism limits him to positing what Weber
called “means-ends rationality” when explaining human action: a modern citizen
could use his reason only to determine what were the most adequate means to
achieve his ends, but those ends themselves could not be subjected to rational
validation. Other way of saying the same thing is that reason (understood as
the systematic application of the scientific method to root out superstition,
bias, fraud and other ways of thinking that are considered by positivist to be
non-rational and, what is essentially the same, unscientific) can tell us how
to act to achieve certain ends, but not to decide what ends we should set for
ourselves (or for others) in the first place. This creates a problem for
complex group, as different individuals are wont to choose different ends, some
of which are likely to be exclusionary (not amenable to being pursued
simultaneously: like if I pursue maximum economic development, ready to
sacrifice whatever it takes to reach it, and you aspire to a maximally clean
and unpolluted environment… our ends would clash and we would have no way to
adjudicate rationally between them). It is a great merit of Parsons to identify
that any “merely” utilitarian system of values (and all positivist
systems end up being utilitarian, as they are left trying to maximize each
individual pleasure -or, alternatively, minimize each individual’s pain, which
is the only thing that is empirical, non-metaphysical and, according to their
understanding of what reality consist of, the only thing that is “real”, and
thus the only valid source of “value”) tends to be unstable, as those “ultimate
ends” are, as I’ve said elsewhere, incommensurable.
So far, so good, we already know
that for utilitarian (and, in more general terms, for all positivistic) systems
there is no place for such thing as “values”, and so it is very difficult to
demonstrate there is something that ultimately matters (in a Parfitian sense). Things are like they are,
happen as they happen (Parsons also notes perceptively that the positivistic
view entails both value neutrality, obviously enough, and determinism,
something with which I also strongly agree), and there is not much we can do
about ‘em, other than note dutifully how they proceed and, at most, show a pro
or con attitude. On top of determinism such outlook ends up resolving itself in
utter relativism: as there is no way to compare my preferred ends with
yours, both being equally valid for each of us (which is the same as saying,
both being equally invalid in the traditional moral sense, because of its
quaint aspiration to universality and unconditionality), the maximum we can
aspire to is a deflationary ethics of tolerance where we endure each other as
best we can, living and letting live as they say, trying to at least respect a
basic set of individual rights in the expectations that our own rights would be
similarly respected. Such lack of common values and common sense of “what
indeed matters” would make the coordination of social groups very difficult and
translate into fragmented, ultra-individualistic societies beset by “anomie”
(an original Durkheimian term). If not killing each other is the best we can
hope for, better to renounce all possible dreams of making great things together
(like ever going to Mars, cheap and plenty fusion energy, or simply maintaining
a planet with a semi-stable climate), as we would be forever doomed to the
suboptimal equilibria we now endure, because of everybody looking out only for
himself, with all the free-riding and externalities we have come to know so
well, and which absent an all-encompassing set of commonly accepted “ultimate ends” we would be
unable to overcome.
Which means that, according to
Durkheim, religion is a necessary component of social cohesion, or at least to
the minimal level of group collaboration required to guarantee a modicum of
human flourishing. Because in the absence of religion, of a common set of
ultimate values that can bind people together and move them towards sacrificing
at least something for the greater good, all we would have is a disparate group
of selfish utility maximizers (pursuing in a more or less enlightened way their
own incommensurable ends, each not admitting of negotiation or compromising
with anybody else’s), Interesting stuff, that contrasts with some other
decidedly (and more vocally) antireligious thinkers which may have shared some of
Durkheim’s outlook, but didn’t have a problem in denying that religion really
needed to have a “real” referent, something really existing to point to (I’m
thinking here on Freud, that similarly was inspired by anthropological
descriptions of Australian totemism but both in Totem and Taboo and The
Future of an Illusion didn’t have any problem deciding that, for all its potential
uses as social agglutinator religion was, as the first title mentioned clearly
implied, an “illusion”, and even worse than that, a symptom of collective
neurosis -it has to be noted that Freud was a notoriously dissembling author,
and his books on religion are specially heavy in unfounded deductive chains and
thinly veiled flights of fancy). Of course, the moment you subtract the element
of truth such practices and sets of beliefs may have you are much less inclined
to attempt to preserve them, and are much more likely to minimize the losses of
getting entirely rid of them.
But what really caught my attention in
all this was its import to my theory of the organization (Organization I, Organization II, Organization III, Decadence of organizations, Organizations & DR), which is one of the
backbones of the book I already mentioned I’m currently working on. if Durkheim’s
understanding of religion (not that different from Freud’s, as I just highlighted)
is correct, that would collapse what I was considering two distinct types of
organization into one: if religion is but an effective way of identifying
members of the group so they can better coordinate with each other, religious
organizations (marked by what they believe is really existing out there, and
the kind of attitude it calls for) and political organizations (marked by the
sense of belonging to a common group, and acting to improve the material lot of
that group against others) would ultimately be the same. There could be no
viable political organization without a distinct and unique set of beliefs that
purported to be about “what there really is” but ultimately were about “who we
are and how we distinguish ourselves from others”.
After thinking hard and long about it, I don’t think Durkheim is right, and I still think it makes sense to keep both types separate, but I’ll need to explain why in another post, as this one has grown beyond my very lax standards already. Stay tuned.
No comments:
Post a Comment